Thomas A. Blackson
Morning, 10/26/2018.
Apparently Socrates
looked
worse.
Philosophy Faculty
Lattie F. Coor Hall, 3356
School of Historical, Philosophical, and Religious Studies
Arizona State University
Tempe, AZ. 85287-4302
USA
Email: blackson@asu.edu
curriculum vitae
Intellectual Biography
I was born in Havre de Grace, Maryland. I went to college in the Midwest. When I graduated, I moved to the Boston area because some friends were moving there. I worked in computers, first as a systems analyst at Instrumentation Laboratory in Lexington, later in the Sloan School at MIT. After a few years, I took a PhD in Philosophy at the University of Massachusetts Amherst. My first academic jobs were visiting positions. I was a Visiting Assistant Professor for two years at North Carolina State University and then for two years at Arizona State University. My first permanent position was at Temple University as an Assistant Professor. After three years, I was promoted with tenure to Associate Professor. I did not like living in the East. When a job came open at Arizona State University, I took a reduction in rank and returned as an Assistant Professor. I enjoyed living there the first time. The desert in Arizona is beautiful. The sky is open and clear blue, and the sunsets and sunrises are spectacular. Two years later, I was tenured and promoted to Associate Professor for a second time.
Academic Research
Service to the Profession:
Managing Editor, Philosophical Studies, 2011-2020
Book Symposium Editor, Philosophical Studies, 2002-present
Recent Teaching:
PHI 328: History of Ancient Philosophy.
An introduction to the philosophical discussion in the Greek and Roman world from 585 BCE to 529 CE.
PHI 333: Introduction to Symbolic Logic.
An introduction to symbolic techniques to represent and evaluate sentences, arguments, and theories.
PHI 420: Topics in the History of Ancient Philosophy.
Hellenistic Epistemology.
PHI 420/581: Studies in Ancient Greek Philosophy.
An investigation into the origin of the notion of free will.
My academic research interests are primarily in Ancient philosophy, although I have
occasionally published work in epistemology and in other areas of contemporary philosophy.
•"Believing for Practical Reasons in Plato's Gorgias"
Rhizomata. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 11, 1 (2023), 105-125.
[abstract]
In Plato’s Gorgias, Socrates says to Callicles that “your love of the people,
existing in your soul, stands against me, but if we closely examine these same
matters often and in a better way, you will be persuaded” (513c7-d1). I argue for
an interpretation that explains how Socrates understands Callicles’s love of the
people to stand against him and why he believes examination often and in a
better way will persuade Callicles.
•"Early Thinking about Likings and Dislikings."
Ancient Philosophy Today: DIALOGO, 4, 2 (2022), 176–195.
[abstract]
In Plato’s Protagoras, Socrates argues that "the many" are confused about the
experience they describe as "being overcome by pleasure." They think the cause is
"something other than ignorance." He argues it follows from what they believe that the
cause is "ignorance" and "false belief." I show that his argument depends on a premise
he does not introduce but they should reject: that when someone is overcome by
pleasure, the desire stems from a belief. To explain why Plato does not make Socrates introduce this premise, the account I construct is speculative. It starts from the assumption that Plato is thinking through an understanding of human beings and what they must do to live good lives that he takes the historical Socrates to set out.
•"Before and After Philosophy Takes Possession of the Soul. The Ascetic
and the Platonic Interpretation."
Journal of Ancient Philosophy, 14, 2 (2020), 53-75.
[abstract]
In the Phaedo, to explain why the philosopher lives in the unusually ascetic way he
does, Socrates explains what someone realizes when philosophy takes possession of
his soul and how he changes his behavior on the basis of this information. This paper
considers the conception of belief the character uses in this explanation and whether
it is the same as the conception Michael Frede thinks the historical Socrates is likely
to have held and that the Stoics much later incorporated into their doctrine of practice.
•"Academic Justifications of Assent"
What the Ancients Offer to Contemporary Epistemology (edited by Stephen
Hetherington and Nicholas D. Smith). Routledge, 2020.
[abstract]
The Clitomachians and the Philonian/Metrodorians responded in different ways
to the challenge the Stoic epistemology posed for the Academic assent to
persuasive impressions. I argue that the Clitomachians did not respond in
terms of the Stoic framework according to which the justification of assent is
a factual property, that the Philonian/Metrodorians did, and that because they
prevailed within the Academy, their response had an important consequence for
the subsequent tradition. It allowed the Stoic conception of justification as
a purely factual matter to enter the tradition without the accompanying
support of the Stoic metaphysics.
•"Plato (ca. 427-ca. 347 B.C.): Apology of Socrates"
AUTOBIOGRAPHY/AUTOFICTION. An International and Interdisciplinary Handbook. Volume
III: Exemplary autobiographical/autofictional texts. Edited by Martina
Wagner-Egelhaaf. De Gruyter, Berlin, 2019. (Submitted 2013.)
[abstract]
I consider the possibility that the Apology is a work of autofiction.
Autofiction is a genre in which the author tries to bring out something
important about a person or a series of events that the author witnessed, but
that the reader would miss in a straightforward historical account. My focus
is on Apology 29c-30b, where Socrates explains what he will not stop
doing.
•"Epicureanism"
The History of Evil,
Volume 1: The History of Evil in Antiquity. 2000 BCE-450 CE (edited by Tom Angier), 163-174.
Routledge, 2018. (Submitted 2012.)
[abstract]
Epicurus did not discuss evil as theological problem. He was interested in the
practical problem of living well, and it is in this connection that Epicurus
made a lasting contribution to understanding evil and its causes. He rejected
the dominate line of thought from the classical tradition of Plato and
Aristotle. Epicurus was an empiricist, not a rationalist. From within this
perspective, he developed a new understanding of the good life.
•"Impulsive Impressions"
Rhizomata. A Journal for Ancient Philosophy and Science, 9 (2017), 91-112.
[abstract]
In the secondary literature, there are two interpretations of how the Stoics
understood impulsive impressions in adults: what I call the "form"
interpretation and the "no-form" interpretation. Brad Inwood and other
historians argue for the form interpretation on the basis of Stobaeus' account
of Stoic ethics. I argue that these arguments are not sound and that the
passages in Stobaeus provide no reason to believe that the form interpretation
is more plausible than the no-form interpretation.
•"The Stoic Explanation for the Origin of Vice"
Méthexis: International Journal for Ancient Philosophy, 29 (2017), 121-140.
[abstract]
The Stoics thought that once human beings become rational, they immediately form
false beliefs about what is good and what is bad. There are no exceptions. Even
the sage once had false beliefs about the value of things. The dispute among the
Stoics was not about whether this happens, but was about how to explain the
reasoning that results in these beliefs. The primary evidence for this dispute
is Galen's discussion in On the Doctrines of Plato and Hippocrates. On
the basis of this discussion and certain assumptions about how the Stoics
understood impulses in the psychology of children and adults, I set out an
interpretation of (i) Chrysippus' explanation of what happens at the onset of
reason when human beings form false beliefs about what is good and what is bad,
(ii) Posidonius' criticism of this explanation of the origin of vice, and (iii)
the explanation that Posidonius himself thought was correct.
•"Against Weatherson on How to Frame a Decision Problem."
Journal of Philosophical Research, 41 (2016), 69-72.
[abstract]
In "Knowledge, Bets, and Interests," Brian Weatherson makes a suggestion for how
to frame a decision problem. He argues that "the states we can 'leave off' a
decision table are the states that the agent knows not to obtain." I present and
defend an example that shows that Weatherson's principle is false.
•"Two Interpretations of Socratic Intellectualism"
Ancient Philosophy, 35 (2015), 23-39.
[abstract]
Among historians of philosophy, Socratic intellectualist psychology has been
understood in at least two ways. On one way (the D interpretation), all
action is a matter of a fixed desire for the good and belief about what the good
is. On another interpretation (the B interpretation), all action is
completely a matter of belief. I argue for the B interpretation of
Socrates' intellectualism in the Protagoras.
•"On Feldman's Theory of Happiness." Utilitas, 21(2009), 393-400.
[abstract]
In Pleasure and the Good Life (OUP, 2004), Fred Feldman argues that
there is a propositional attitude (he calls "attitudinal pleasure/displeasure")
expressed in ordinary uses of sentences of the form 'S is pleased/displeased
that P.' He distinguishes intrinsic from extrinsic attitudinal
pleasure and displeasure, and he excludes extrinsic attitudinal
pleasure/displeasure from the aggregation of attitudinal pleasure/displeasure
that constitutes happiness. I argue that Feldman has not made a strong case for
this distinction and exclusion.
•"On Williamson's Argument for (Ii) in his Anti-luminosity Argument."
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74 (2007), 397-405.
[abstract]
Williamson's anti-luminosity argument depends on what he says is an "intuitive"
connection between knowledge and reliability. (Knowledge and its Limits
(OUP, 2000), 100.) I believe that the connection is "intuitive," although this
can take some time to see, but I argue that this "intuitive" connection is not
sufficient to support (Ii) in his anti-luminosity argument.
Williamson's argument against luminosity is not sound.
•"In Defense of an Unpopular Interpretation of Ancient Skepticism."
Logical Analysis and the History of Philosophy: History of Epistemology, 8 (2005), 68-81.
[abstract]
The subject of this paper is the history of late Academic Skepticism and its
connection to the emergence of Pyrrhonian Skepticism. The two main ways to
understand this period in history are anthologized in The Original Sceptics:
A Controversy (Hackett Publishing Company, 1977), edited by Myles Burnyeat
and Michael Frede. To many, Frede's position has been less convincing to many
than Burnyeat's. Frede argues that life without belief was not a fundamental
feature of Pyrrhonism. Frede presents his arguments somewhat confusingly, which
has made his interpretation difficult to appreciate, but I argue that there is
more to be said for Frede's interpretation than has been thought. I argue that
Frede's interpretation, when properly understood, shows that the ancient
skeptics in the Clitomachian-Pyrrhonian tradition are fallibilists who took the
first steps in working out the view that epistemic justification is a matter of
whether a belief is the outcome of a correct cognitive process and that
correctness here need not be understood in terms of a reliable connection to
truth.
•"An Invalid Argument for Contextualism."
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 68 (2004), 344-345.
[abstract]
In "Assertion, Knowledge, and Context" (Philosophical Review, Vol. 111,
No. 2 (April 2002), 167-203), Keith DeRose argues for contexualism as follows.
"The knowledge account assertion provides a powerful argument for contextualism:
if the standards for when one is in a position to warrantedly assert that P are
the same as those what comprise a truth-condition for 'I know P,' then if the
former vary with context, so do the latter. In short: The knowledge account of
assertion together with the context-sensitivity of assertability yields
contextualism about knowledge" (187). I show that this argument is invalid.